´óÏã½¶É«È˸ó

    1. <form id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ></nobr></form>
      <address id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ><nobr id=LYiWIujZJ></nobr></nobr></address>

      Source: New Republic
      Date: Vol. 216 Issue 22 (June 2, 1997).

      The Wisdom of Repugnance

      LEON R. KASS

      If we should not underestimate the significance of human cloning, neither
      should we exaggerate its imminence or misunderstand just what is involved.

      Our habit of delighting in news of scientific and technological breakthroughs has been sorely challenged by the birth announcement of a sheep named Dolly. Though Dolly shares with previous sheep the ¡°softest clothing, woolly, bright,¡± William Blake¡¯s question, ¡°Little Lamb, who made thee?¡± has for her a radically different answer: Dolly was, quite literally, made. She is the work not of nature or nature¡¯s God but of man, an Englishman, Ian Wilmut, and his fellow scientists. What¡¯s more, Dolly came into being not only asexually ¡ª ironically, just like ¡°He [who] calls Himself a Lamb¡± ¡ª but also as the genetically identical copy (and the perfect incarnation of the form or blueprint) of a mature ewe, of whom she is a clone. This long-awaited yet not quite expected success in cloning a mammal raised immediately the prospect ¡ª and the specter ¡ª of cloning human beings: ¡°I a child and Thou a lamb,¡± despite our differences, have always been equal candidates for creative making, only now, by means of cloning, we may both spring from the hand of man playing at being God.

      After an initial flurry of expert comment and public consternation, with opinion polls showing overwhelming opposition to cloning human beings, President Clinton ordered a ban on all federal support for human cloning research (even though none was being supported) and charged the National Bioethics Advisory Commission to report in ninety days on the ethics of human cloning research. The commission (an eighteen-member panel, evenly balanced between scientists and nonscientists, appointed by the president and reporting to the National Science and Technology Council) invited testimony from scientists, religious thinkers and bioethicists, as well as from the general public. It is now deliberating about what it should recommend, both as a matter of ethics and as a matter of public policy.

      Congress is awaiting the commission¡¯s report, and is poised to act. Bills to prohibit the use of federal funds for human cloning research have been introduced in the House of Representatives and the Senate; and another bill, in the House, would make it illegal ¡°for any person to use a human somatic cell for the process of producing a human clone.¡± A fateful decision is at hand. To clone or not to clone a human being is no longer an academic question.

      Taking cloning seriously, then and now

      Cloning first came to public attention roughly thirty years ago, following the successful asexual production, in England, of a clutch of tadpole clones by the technique of nuclear transplantation. The individual largely responsible for bringing the prospect and promise of human cloning to public notice was Joshua Lederberg, a Nobel Laureate geneticist and a man of large vision. In 1966, Lederberg wrote a remarkable article in The American Naturalist detailing the eugenic advantages of human cloning and other forms of genetic engineering, and the following year he devoted a column in The Washington Post, where he wrote regularly on science and society, to the prospect of human cloning. He suggested that cloning could help us overcome the unpredictable variety that still rules human reproduction, and allow us to benefit from perpetuating superior genetic endowments. These writings sparked a small public debate in which I became a participant. At the time a young researcher in molecular biology at the National Institutes of Health (NIH), I wrote a reply to the Post, arguing against Lederberg¡¯s amoral treatment of this morally weighty subject and insisting on the urgency of confronting a series of questions and objections, culminating in the suggestion that ¡°the programmed reproduction of man will, in fact, dehumanize him.¡±

      Much has happened in the intervening years. It has become harder, not easier, to discern the true meaning of human cloning. We have in some sense been softened up to the idea ¡ª through movies, cartoons, jokes and intermittent commentary in the mass media, some serious, most lighthearted. We have become accustomed to new practices in human reproduction: not just in vitro fertilization, but also embryo manipulation, embryo donation and surrogate pregnancy. Animal biotechnology has yielded transgenic animals and a burgeoning science of genetic engineering, easily and soon to be transferable to humans.

      Even more important, changes in the broader culture make it now vastly more difficult to express a common and respectful understanding of sexuality, procreation, nascent life, family, and the meaning of motherhood, fatherhood and the links between the generations. Twenty-five years ago, abortion was still largely illegal and thought to be immoral, the sexual revolution (made possible by the extramarital use of the pill) was still in its infancy, and few had yet heard about the reproductive rights of single women, homosexual men and lesbians. (Never mind shameless memoirs about one¡¯s own incest!) Then one could argue, without embarrassment, that the new technologies of human reproduction ¡ª babies without sex ¡ª and their confounding of normal kin relations ¡ª who¡¯s the mother: the egg donor, the surrogate who carries and delivers, or the one who rears? ¡ª would ¡°undermine the justification and support that biological parenthood gives to the monogamous marriage.¡± Today, defenders of stable, monogamous marriage risk charges of giving offense to those adults who are living in ¡°new family forms¡± or to those children who, even without the benefit of assisted reproduction, have acquired either three or four parents or one or none at all. Today, one must even apologize for voicing opinions that twenty-five years ago were nearly universally regarded as the core of our culture¡¯s wisdom on these matters. In a world whose once-given natural boundaries are blurred by technological change and whose moral boundaries are seemingly up for grabs, it is much more difficult to make persuasive the still compelling case against cloning human beings. As Raskolnikov put it, ¡°man gets used to everything ¡ª the beast!¡±

      Indeed, perhaps the most depressing feature of the discussions that immediately followed the news about Dolly was their ironical tone, their genial cynicism, their moral fatigue: ¡°AN UDDER WAY OF MAKING LAMBS¡± (Nature), ¡°WHO WILL CASH IN ON BREAKTHROUGH IN CLONING?¡± (The Wall Street Journal), ¡°IS CLONING BAAAAAAAAD?¡± (The Chicago Tribune). Gone from the scene are the wise and courageous voices of Theodosius Dobzhansky (genetics), Hans Jonas (philosophy) and Paul Ramsey (theology) who, only twenty-five years ago, all made powerful moral arguments against ever cloning a human being. We are now too sophisticated for such argumentation; we wouldn¡¯t be caught in public with a strong moral stance, never mind an absolutist one. We are all, or almost all, post-modernists now.

      Cloning turns out to be the perfect embodiment of the ruling opinions of our new age. Thanks to the sexual revolution, we are able to deny in practice, and increasingly in thought, the inherent procreative teleology of sexuality itself. But, if sex has no intrinsic connection to generating babies, babies need have no necessary connection to sex. Thanks to feminism and the gay rights movement, we are increasingly encouraged to treat the natural heterosexual difference and its preeminence as a matter of ¡°cultural construction.¡± But if male and female are not normatively complementary and generatively significant, babies need not come from male and female complementarity. Thanks to the prominence and the acceptability of divorce and out-of-wedlock births, stable, monogamous marriage as the ideal home for procreation is no longer the agreed-upon cultural norm. For this new dispensation, the clone is the ideal emblem: the ultimate ¡°single-parent child.¡±

      Thanks to our belief that all children should be wanted children (the more high-minded principle we use to justify contraception and abortion), sooner or later only those children who fulfill our wants will be fully acceptable. Through cloning, we can work our wants and wills on the very identity of our children, exercising control as never before. Thanks to modern notions of individualism and the rate of cultural change, we see ourselves not as linked to ancestors and defined by traditions, but as projects for our own self-creation, not only as self-made men but also man-made selves; and self-cloning is simply an extension of such rootless and narcissistic self-recreation.

      Unwilling to acknowledge our debt to the past and unwilling to embrace the uncertainties and the limitations of the future, we have a false relation to both: cloning personifies our desire fully to control the future, while being subject to no controls ourselves. Enchanted and enslaved by the glamour of technology, we have lost our awe and wonder before the deep mysteries of nature and of life. We cheerfully take our own beginnings in our hands and, like the last man, we blink.

      Part of the blame for our complacency lies, sadly, with the field of bioethics itself, and its claim to expertise in these moral matters. Bioethics was founded by people who understood that the new biology touched and threatened the deepest matters of our humanity: bodily integrity, identity and individuality, lineage and kinship, freedom and self-command, eros and aspiration, and the relations and strivings of body and soul. With its capture by analytic philosophy, however, and its inevitable routinization and professionalization, the field has by and large come to content itself with analyzing moral arguments, reacting to new technological developments and taking on emerging issues of public policy, all performed with a naive faith that the evils we fear can all be avoided by compassion, regulation and a respect for autonomy. Bioethics has made some major contributions in the protection of human subjects and in other areas where personal freedom is threatened; but its practitioners, with few exceptions, have turned the big human questions into pretty thin gruel.

      One reason for this is that the piecemeal formation of public policy tends to grind down large questions of morals into small questions of procedure. Many of the country¡¯s leading bioethicists have served on national commissions or state task forces and advisory boards, where, understandably, they have found utilitarianism to be the only ethical vocabulary acceptable to all participants in discussing issues of law, regulation and public policy. As many of these commissions have been either officially under the aegis of NIH or the Health and Human Services Department, or otherwise dominated by powerful voices for scientific progress, the ethicists have for the most part been content, after some ¡°values clarification¡± and wringing of hands, to pronounce their blessings upon the inevitable. Indeed, it is the bioethicists, not the scientists, who are now the most articulate defenders of human cloning: the two witnesses testifying before the National Bioethics Advisory Commission in favor of cloning human beings were bioethicists, eager to rebut what they regard as the irrational concerns of those of us in opposition. One wonders whether this commission, constituted like the previous commissions, can tear itself sufficiently free from the accommodationist pattern of rubber-stamping all technical innovation, in the mistaken belief that all other goods must bow down before the gods of better health and scientific advance.

      If it is to do so, the commission must first persuade itself, as we all should persuade ourselves, not to be complacent about what is at issue here. Human cloning, though it is in some respects continuous with previous reproductive technologies, also represents something radically new, in itself and in its easily foreseeable consequences. The stakes are very high indeed. I exaggerate, but in the direction of the truth, when I insist that we are faced with having to decide nothing less than whether human procreation is going to remain human, whether children are going to be made rather than begotten, whether it is a good thing, humanly speaking, to say yes in principle to the road which leads (at best) to the dehumanized rationality of Brave New World. This is not business as usual, to be fretted about for a while but finally to be given our seal of approval. We must rise to the occasion and make our judgments as if the future of our humanity hangs in the balance. For so it does.

      The state of the art

      If we should not underestimate the significance of human cloning, neither should we exaggerate its imminence or misunderstand just what is involved. The procedure is conceptually simple. The nucleus of a mature but unfertilized egg is removed and replaced with a nucleus obtained from a specialized cell of an adult (or fetal) organism (in Dolly¡¯s case, the donor nucleus came from mammary gland epithelium). Since almost all the hereditary material of a cell is contained within its nucleus, the renucleated egg and the individual into which this egg develops are genetically identical to the organism that was the source of the transferred nucleus. An unlimited number of genetically identical individuals ¡ª clones ¡ª could be produced by nuclear transfer. In principle, any person, male or female, newborn or adult, could be cloned, and in any quantity. With laboratory cultivation and storage of tissues, cells outliving their sources make it possible even to clone the dead.

      The technical stumbling block, overcome by Wilmut and his colleagues, was to find a means of reprogramming the state of the DNA in the donor cells, reversing its differentiated expression and restoring its full totipotency, so that it could again direct the entire process of producing a mature organism. Now that this problem has been solved, we should expect a rush to develop cloning for other animals, especially livestock, in order to propagate in perpetuity the champion meat or milk producers. Though exactly how soon someone will succeed in cloning a human being is anybody¡¯s guess, Wilmut¡¯s technique, almost certainly applicable to humans, makes attempting the feat an imminent possibility.

      Yet some cautions are in order and some possible misconceptions need correcting. For a start, cloning is not Xeroxing. As has been reassuringly reiterated, the clone of Mel Gibson, though his genetic double, would enter the world hairless, toothless and peeing in his diapers, just like any other human infant. Moreover, the success rate, at least at first, will probably not be very high: the British transferred 277 adult nuclei into enucleated sheep eggs, and implanted twenty-nine clonal embryos, but they achieved the birth of only one live lamb clone. For this reason, among others, it is unlikely that, at least for now, the practice would be very popular, and there is no immediate worry of mass-scale production of multicopies. The need of repeated surgery to obtain eggs and, more crucially, of numerous borrowed wombs for implantation will surely limit use, as will the expense; besides, almost everyone who is able will doubtless prefer nature¡¯s sexier way of conceiving.

      Still, for the tens of thousands of people already sustaining over 200 assisted-reproduction clinics in the United States and already availing themselves of in vitro fertilization, intracytoplasmic sperm injection and other techniques of assisted reproduction, cloning would be an option with virtually no added fuss (especially when the success rate improves). Should commercial interests develop in ¡°nucleus-banking,¡± as they have in sperm-banking; should famous athletes or other celebrities decide to market their DNA the way they now market their autographs and just about everything else; should techniques of embryo and germline genetic testing and manipulation arrive as anticipated, increasing the use of laboratory assistance in order to obtain ¡°better¡± babies ¡ª should all this come to pass, then cloning, if it is permitted, could become more than a marginal practice simply on the basis of free reproductive choice, even without any social encouragement to upgrade the gene pool or to replicate superior types. Moreover, if laboratory research on human cloning proceeds, even without any intention to produce cloned humans, the existence of cloned human embryos in the laboratory, created to begin with only for research purposes, would surely pave the way for later baby-making implantations.

      In anticipation of human cloning, apologists and proponents have already made clear possible uses of the perfected technology, ranging from the sentimental and compassionate to the grandiose. They include: providing a child for an infertile couple; ¡°replacing¡± a beloved spouse or child who is dying or has died; avoiding the risk of genetic disease; permitting reproduction for homosexual men and lesbians who want nothing sexual to do with the opposite sex; securing a genetically identical source of organs or tissues perfectly suitable for transplantation; getting a child with a genotype of one¡¯s own choosing, not excluding oneself; replicating individuals of great genius, talent or beauty ¡ª having a child who really could ¡°be like Mike¡±; and creating large sets of genetically identical humans suitable for research on, for instance, the question of nature versus nurture, or for special missions in peace and war (not excluding espionage), in which using identical humans would be an advantage. Most people who envision the cloning of human beings, of course, want none of these scenarios. That they cannot say why is not surprising. What is surprising, and welcome, is that, in our cynical age, they are saying anything at all.

      The wisdom of repugnance

      ¡°Offensive.¡± ¡°Grotesque.¡± ¡°Revolting.¡± ¡°Repugnant.¡± ¡°Repulsive.¡± These are the words most commonly heard regarding the prospect of human cloning. Such reactions come both from the man or woman in the street and from the intellectuals, from believers and atheists, from humanists and scientists. Even Dolly¡¯s creator has said he ¡°would find it offensive¡± to clone a human being.

      People are repelled by many aspects of human cloning. They recoil from the prospect of mass production of human beings, with large clones of look-alikes, compromised in their individuality; the idea of father-son or mother-daughter twins; the bizarre prospects of a woman giving birth to and rearing a genetic copy of herself, her spouse or even her deceased father or mother; the grotesqueness of conceiving a child as an exact replacement for another who has died; the utilitarian creation of embryonic genetic duplicates of oneself, to be frozen away or created when necessary, in case of need for homologous tissues or organs for transplantation; the narcissism of those who would clone themselves and the arrogance of others who think they know who deserves to be cloned or which genotype any child-to-be should be thrilled to receive; the Frankensteinian hubris to create human life and increasingly to control its destiny; man playing God. Almost no one finds any of the suggested reasons for human cloning compelling; almost everyone anticipates its possible misuses and abuses. Moreover, many people feel oppressed by the sense that there is probably nothing we can do to prevent it from happening. This makes the prospect all the more revolting.

      Revulsion is not an argument; and some of yesterday¡¯s repugnances are today calmly accepted ¡ª though, one must add, not always for the better. In crucial cases, however, repugnance is the emotional expression of deep wisdom, beyond reason¡¯s power fully to articulate it. Can anyone really give an argument fully adequate to the horror which is father-daughter incest (even with consent), or having sex with animals, or mutilating a corpse, or eating human flesh, or even just (just!) raping or murdering another human being? Would anybody¡¯s failure to give full rational justification for his or her revulsion at these practices make that revulsion ethically suspect? Not at all. On the contrary, we are suspicious of those who think that they can rationalize away our horror, say, by trying to explain the enormity of incest with arguments only about the genetic risks of inbreeding.

      The repugnance at human cloning belongs in this category. We are repelled by the prospect of cloning human beings not because of the strangeness or novelty of the undertaking, but because we intuit and feel, immediately and without argument, the violation of things that we rightfully hold dear. Repugnance, here as elsewhere, revolts against the excesses of human willfulness, warning us not to transgress what is unspeakably profound. Indeed, in this age in which everything is held to be permissible so long as it is freely done, in which our given human nature no longer commands respect, in which our bodies are regarded as mere instruments of our autonomous rational wills, repugnance may be the only voice left that speaks up to defend the central core of our humanity. Shallow are the souls that have forgotten how to shudder.

      The goods protected by repugnance are generally overlooked by our customary ways of approaching all new biomedical technologies. The way we evaluate cloning ethically will in fact be shaped by how we characterize it descriptively, by the context into which we place it, and by the perspective from which we view it. The first task for ethics is proper description. And here is where our failure begins.

      Typically, cloning is discussed in one or more of three familiar contexts, which one might call the technological, the liberal and the meliorist. Under the first, cloning will be seen as an extension of existing techniques for assisting reproduction and determining the genetic makeup of children. Like them, cloning is to be regarded as a neutral technique, with no inherent meaning or goodness, but subject to multiple uses, some good, some bad. The morality of cloning thus depends absolutely on the goodness or badness of the motives and intentions of the cloners: as one bioethicist defender of cloning puts it, ¡°the ethics must be judged [only] by the way the parents nurture and rear their resulting child and whether they bestow the same love and affection on a child brought into existence by a technique of assisted reproduction as they would on a child born in the usual way.¡±

      The liberal (or libertarian or liberationist) perspective sets cloning in the context of rights, freedoms and personal empowerment. Cloning is just a new option for exercising an individual¡¯s right to reproduce or to have the kind of child that he or she wants. Alternatively, cloning enhances our liberation (especially women¡¯s liberation) from the confines of nature, the vagaries of chance, or the necessity for sexual mating. Indeed, it liberates women from the need for men altogether, for the process requires only eggs, nuclei and (for the time being) uteri ¡ª plus, of course, a healthy dose of our (allegedly ¡°masculine¡±) manipulative science that likes to do all these things to mother nature and nature¡¯s mothers. For those who hold this outlook, the only moral restraints on cloning are adequately informed consent and the avoidance of bodily harm. If no one is cloned without her consent, and if the clonant is not physically damaged, then the liberal conditions for licit, hence moral, conduct are met. Worries that go beyond violating the will or maiming the body are dismissed as ¡°symbolic¡± ¡ª which is to say, unreal.

      The meliorist perspective embraces valetudinarians and also eugenicists. The latter were formerly more vocal in these discussions, but they are now generally happy to see their goals advanced under the less threatening banners of freedom and technological growth. These people see in cloning a new prospect for improving human beings ¡ª minimally, by ensuring the perpetuation of healthy individuals by avoiding the risks of genetic disease inherent in the lottery of sex, and maximally, by producing ¡°optimum babies,¡± preserving outstanding genetic material, and (with the help of soon-to-come techniques for precise genetic engineering) enhancing inborn human capacities on many fronts. Here the morality of cloning as a means is justified solely by the excellence of the end, that is, by the outstanding traits or individuals cloned ¡ª beauty, or brawn, or brains.

      These three approaches, all quintessentially American and all perfectly fine in their places, are sorely wanting as approaches to human procreation. It is, to say the least, grossly distorting to view the wondrous mysteries of birth, renewal and individuality, and the deep meaning of parent-child relations, largely through the lens of our reductive science and its potent technologies. Similarly, considering reproduction (and the intimate relations of family life!) primarily under the political-legal, adversarial and individualistic notion of rights can only undermine the private yet fundamentally social, cooperative and duty-laden character of child-bearing, child-rearing and their bond to the covenant of marriage. Seeking to escape entirely from nature (in order to satisfy a natural desire or a natural right to reproduce!) is self-contradictory in theory and self-alienating in practice. For we are erotic beings only because we are embodied beings, and not merely intellects and wills unfortunately imprisoned in our bodies. And, though health and fitness are clearly great goods, there is something deeply disquieting in looking on our prospective children as artful products perfectible by genetic engineering, increasingly held to our willfully imposed designs, specifications and margins of tolerable error.

      The technical, liberal and meliorist approaches all ignore the deeper anthropological, social and, indeed, ontological meanings of bringing forth new life. To this more fitting and profound point of view, cloning shows itself to be a major alteration, indeed, a major violation, of our given nature as embodied, gendered and engendering beings ¡ª and of the social relations built on this natural ground. Once this perspective is recognized, the ethical judgment on cloning can no longer be reduced to a matter of motives and intentions, rights and freedoms, benefits and harms, or even means and ends. It must be regarded primarily as a matter of meaning: Is cloning a fulfillment of human begetting and belonging? Or is cloning rather, as I contend, their pollution and perversion? To pollution and perversion, the fitting response can only be horror and revulsion; and conversely, generalized horror and revulsion are prima facie evidence of foulness and violation. The burden of moral argument must fall entirely on those who want to declare the widespread repugnances of humankind to be mere timidity or superstition. Yet repugnance need not stand naked before the bar of reason. The wisdom of our horror at human cloning can be partially articulated, even if this is finally one of those instances about which the heart has its reasons that reason cannot entirely know.

      The profundity of sex

      To see cloning in its proper context, we must begin not, as I did before, with laboratory technique, but with the anthropology ¡ª natural and social ¡ª of sexual reproduction.

      Sexual reproduction ¡ª by which I mean the generation of new life from (exactly) two complementary elements, one female, one male, (usually) through coitus ¡ª is established (if that is the right term) not by human decision, culture or tradition, but by nature; it is the natural way of all mammalian reproduction. By nature, each child has two complementary biological progenitors. Each child thus stems from and unites exactly two lineages. In natural generation, moreover, the precise genetic constitution of the resulting offspring is determined by a combination of nature and chance, not by human design: each human child shares the common natural human species genotype, each child is genetically (equally) kin to each (both) parent(s), yet each child is also genetically unique.

      These biological truths about our origins foretell deep truths about our identity and about our human condition altogether. Every one of us is at once equally human, equally enmeshed in a particular familial nexus of origin, and equally individuated in our trajectory from birth to death ¡ª and, if all goes well, equally capable (despite our mortality) of participating, with a complementary other, in the very same renewal of such human possibility through procreation. Though less momentous than our common humanity, our genetic individuality is not humanly trivial. It shows itself forth in our distinctive appearance through which we are everywhere recognized; it is revealed in our ¡°signature¡± marks of fingerprints and our self-recognizing immune system; it symbolizes and foreshadows exactly the unique, never-to-be-repeated character of each human life.

      Human societies virtually everywhere have structured child-rearing responsibilities and systems of identity and relationship on the bases of these deep natural facts of begetting. The mysterious yet ubiquitous ¡°love of one¡¯s own¡± is everywhere culturally exploited, to make sure that children are not just produced but well cared for and to create for everyone clear ties of meaning, belonging and obligation. But it is wrong to treat such naturally rooted social practices as mere cultural constructs (like left-or right-driving, or like burying or cremating the dead) that we can alter with little human cost. What would kinship be without its clear natural grounding? And what would identity be without kinship? We must resist those who have begun to refer to sexual reproduction as the ¡°traditional method of reproduction,¡± who would have us regard as merely traditional, and by implication arbitrary, what is in truth not only natural but most certainly profound.

      Asexual reproduction, which produces ¡°single-parent¡± offspring, is a radical departure from the natural human way, confounding all normal understandings of father, mother, sibling, grandparent, etc., and all moral relations tied thereto. It becomes even more of a radical departure when the resulting offspring is a clone derived not from an embryo, but from a mature adult to whom the clone would be an identical twin; and when the process occurs not by natural accident (as in natural twinning), but by deliberate human design and manipulation; and when the child¡¯s (or children¡¯s) genetic constitution is pre-selected by the parent(s) (or scientists). Accordingly, as we will see, cloning is vulnerable to three kinds of concerns and objections, related to these three points: cloning threatens confusion of identity and individuality, even in small-scale cloning; cloning represents a giant step (though not the first one) toward transforming procreation into manufacture, that is, toward the increasing depersonalization of the process of generation and, increasingly, toward the ¡°production¡± of human children as artifacts, products of human will and design (what others have called the problem of ¡°commodification¡± of new life); and cloning ¡ª like other forms of eugenic engineering of the next generation ¡ª represents a form of despotism of the cloners over the cloned, and thus (even in benevolent cases) represents a blatant violation of the inner meaning of parent-child relations, of what it means to have a child, of what it means to say ¡°yes¡± to our own demise and ¡°replacement.¡±

      Before turning to these specific ethical objections, let me test my claim of the profundity of the natural way by taking up a challenge recently posed by a friend. What if the given natural human way of reproduction were asexual, and we now had to deal with a new technological innovation ¡ª artificially induced sexual dimorphism and the fusing of complementary gametes ¡ª whose inventors argued that sexual reproduction promised all sorts of advantages, including hybrid vigor and the creation of greatly increased individuality? Would one then be forced to defend natural asexuality because it was natural? Could one claim that it carried deep human meaning?

      The response to this challenge broaches the ontological meaning of sexual reproduction. For it is impossible, I submit, for there to have been human life ¡ª or even higher forms of animal life ¡ª in the absence of sexuality and sexual reproduction. We find asexual reproduction only in the lowest forms of life: bacteria, algae, fungi, some lower invertebrates. Sexuality brings with it a new and enriched relationship to the world. Only sexual animals can seek and find complementary others with whom to pursue a goal that transcends their own existence. For a sexual being, the world is no longer an indifferent and largely homogeneous otherness, in part edible, in part dangerous. It also contains some very special and related and complementary beings, of the same kind but of opposite sex, toward whom one reaches out with special interest and intensity. In higher birds and mammals, the outward gaze keeps a lookout not only for food and predators, but also for prospective mates; the beholding of the many splendored world is suffused with desire for union, the animal antecedent of human eros and the germ of sociality. Not by accident is the human animal both the sexiest animal ¡ª whose females do not go into heat but are receptive throughout the estrous cycle and whose males must therefore have greater sexual appetite and energy in order to reproduce successfully ¡ª and also the most aspiring, the most social, the most open and the most intelligent animal.

      The soul-elevating power of sexuality is, at bottom, rooted in its strange connection to mortality, which it simultaneously accepts and tries to overcome. Asexual reproduction may be seen as a continuation of the activity of self-preservation. When one organism buds or divides to become two, the original being is (doubly) preserved, and nothing dies. Sexuality, by contrast, means perishability and serves replacement; the two that come together to generate one soon will die. Sexual desire, in human beings as in animals, thus serves an end that is partly hidden from, and finally at odds with, the self-serving individual. Whether we know it or not, when we are sexually active we are voting with our genitalia for our own demise. The salmon swimming upstream to spawn and die tell the universal story: sex is bound up with death, to which it holds a partial answer in procreation.

      The salmon and the other animals evince this truth blindly. Only the human being can understand what it means. As we learn so powerfully from the story of the Garden of Eden, our humanization is coincident with sexual self-consciousness, with the recognition of our sexual nakedness and all that it implies: shame at our needy incompleteness, unruly self-division and finitude; awe before the eternal; hope in the self-transcending possibilities of children and a relationship to the divine. In the sexually self-conscious animal, sexual desire can become eros, lust can become love. Sexual desire humanly regarded is thus sublimated into erotic longing for wholeness, completion and immortality, which drives us knowingly into the embrace and its generative fruit ¡ª as well as into all the higher human possibilities of deed, speech and song.

      Through children, a good common to both husband and wife, male and female achieve some genuine unification (beyond the mere sexual ¡°union,¡± which fails to do so). The two become one through sharing generous (not needy) love for this third being as good. Flesh of their flesh, the child is the parents¡¯ own commingled being externalized, and given a separate and persisting existence. Unification is enhanced also by their commingled work of rearing. Providing an opening to the future beyond the grave, carrying not only our seed but also our names, our ways and our hopes that they will surpass us in goodness and happiness, children are a testament to the possibility of transcendence. Gender duality and sexual desire, which first draws our love upward and outside of ourselves, finally provide for the partial overcoming of the confinement and limitation of perishable embodiment altogether.

      Human procreation, in sum, is not simply an activity of our rational wills. It is a more complete activity precisely because it engages us bodily, erotically and spiritually, as well as rationally. There is wisdom in the mystery of nature that has joined the pleasure of sex, the inarticulate longing for union, the communication of the loving embrace and the deep-seated and only partly articulate desire for children in the very activity by which we continue the chain of human existence and participate in the renewal of human possibility. Whether or not we know it, the severing of procreation from sex, love and intimacy is inherently dehumanizing, no matter how good the product.

      We are now ready for the more specific objections to cloning.

      The perversities of clining

      First, an important if formal objection: any attempt to clone a human being would constitute an unethical experiment upon the resulting child-to-be. As the animal experiments (frog and sheep) indicate, there are grave risks of mishaps and deformities. Moreover, because of what cloning means, one cannot presume a future cloned child¡¯s consent to be a clone, even a healthy one. Thus, ethically speaking, we cannot even get to know whether or not human cloning is feasible.

      I understand, of course, the philosophical difficulty of trying to compare a life with defects against nonexistence. Several bioethicists, proud of their philosophical cleverness, use this conundrum to embarrass claims that one can injure a child in its conception, precisely because it is only thanks to that complained-of conception that the child is alive to complain. But common sense tells us that we have no reason to fear such philosophisms. For we surely know that people can harm and even maim children in the very act of conceiving them, say, by paternal transmission of the AIDS virus, maternal transmission of heroin dependence or, arguably, even by bringing them into being as bastards or with no capacity or willingness to look after them properly. And we believe that to do this intentionally, or even negligently, is inexcusable and clearly unethical.

      The objection about the impossibility of presuming consent may even go beyond the obvious and sufficient point that a clonant, were he subsequently to be asked, could rightly resent having been made a clone. At issue are not just benefits and harms, but doubts about the very independence needed to give proper (even retroactive) consent, that is, not just the capacity to choose but the disposition and ability to choose freely and well. It is not at all clear to what extent a clone will truly be a moral agent. For, as we shall see, in the very fact of cloning, and of rearing him as a clone, his makers subvert the cloned child¡¯s independence, beginning with that aspect that comes from knowing that one was an unbidden surprise, a gift, to the world, rather than the designed result of someone¡¯s artful project.

      Cloning creates serious issues of identity and individuality. The cloned person may experience concerns about his distinctive identity not only because he will be in genotype and appearance identical to another human being, but, in this case, because he may also be twin to the person who is his ¡°father¡± or ¡°mother¡± ¡ª if one can still call them that. What would be the psychic burdens of being the ¡°child¡± or ¡°parent¡± of your twin? The cloned individual, moreover, will be saddled with a genotype that has already lived. He will not be fully a surprise to the world. People are likely always to compare his performances in life with that of his alter ego. True, his nurture and his circumstance in life will be different; genotype is not exactly destiny. Still, one must also expect parental and other efforts to shape this new life after the original ¡ª or at least to view the child with the original version always firmly in mind. Why else did they clone from the star basketball player, mathematician and beauty queen ¡ª or even dear old dad ¡ª in the first place?

      Since the birth of Dolly, there has been a fair amount of doublespeak on this matter of genetic identity. Experts have rushed in to reassure the public that the clone would in no way be the same person, or have any confusions about his or her identity: as previously noted, they are pleased to point out that the clone of Mel Gibson would not be Mel Gibson. Fair enough. But one is shortchanging the truth by emphasizing the additional importance of the intrauterine environment, rearing and social setting: genotype obviously matters plenty. That, after all, is the only reason to clone, whether human beings or sheep. The odds that clones of Wilt Chamberlain will play in the NBA are, I submit, infinitely greater than they are for clones of Robert Reich.

      Curiously, this conclusion is supported, inadvertently, by the one ethical sticking point insisted on by friends of cloning: no cloning without the donor¡¯s consent. Though an orthodox liberal objection, it is in fact quite puzzling when it comes from people (such as Ruth Macklin) who also insist that genotype is not identity or individuality, and who deny that a child could reasonably complain about being made a genetic copy. If the clone of Mel Gibson would not be Mel Gibson, why should Mel Gibson have grounds to object that someone had been made his clone? We already allow researchers to use blood and tissue samples for research purposes of no benefit to their sources: my falling hair, my expectorations, my urine and even my biopsied tissues are ¡°not me¡± and not mine. Courts have held that the profit gained from uses to which scientists put my discarded tissues do not legally belong to me. Why, then, no cloning without consent ¡ª including, I assume, no cloning from the body of someone who just died? What harm is done the donor, if genotype is ¡°not me¡±? Truth to tell, the only powerful justification for objecting is that genotype really does have something to do with identity, and everybody knows it. If not, on what basis could Michael Jordan object that someone cloned ¡°him,¡± say, from cells taken from a ¡°lost¡± scraped-off piece of his skin? The insistence on donor consent unwittingly reveals the problem of identity in all cloning.

      Genetic distinctiveness not only symbolizes the uniqueness of each human life and the independence of its parents that each human child rightfully attains. It can also be an important support for living a worthy and dignified life. Such arguments apply with great force to any large-scale replication of human individuals. But they are sufficient, in my view, to rebut even the first attempts to clone a human being. One must never forget that these are human beings upon whom our eugenic or merely playful fantasies are to be enacted.

      Troubled psychic identity (distinctiveness), based on all-too-evident genetic identity (sameness), will be made much worse by the utter confusion of social identity and kinship ties. For, as already noted, cloning radically confounds lineage and social relations, for ¡°offspring¡± as for ¡°parents.¡± As bioethicist James Nelson has pointed out, a female child cloned from her ¡°mother¡± might develop a desire for a relationship to her ¡°father,¡± and might understandably seek out the father of her ¡°mother,¡± who is after all also her biological twin sister. Would ¡°grandpa,¡± who thought his paternal duties concluded, be pleased to discover that the clonant looked to him for paternal attention and support?

      Social identity and social ties of relationship and responsibility are widely connected to, and supported by, biological kinship. Social taboos on incest (and adultery) everywhere serve to keep clear who is related to whom (and especially which child belongs to which parents), as well as to avoid confounding the social identity of parent-and-child (or brother-and-sister) with the social identity of lovers, spouses and co-parents. True, social identity is altered by adoption (but as a matter of the best interest of already living children: we do not deliberately produce children for adoption). True, artificial insemination and in vitro fertilization with donor sperm, or whole embryo donation, are in some way forms of ¡°prenatal adoption¡± ¡ª a not altogether unproblematic practice. Even here, though, there is in each case (as in all sexual reproduction) a known male source of sperm and a known single female source of egg ¡ª a genetic father and a genetic mother ¡ª should anyone care to know (as adopted children often do) who is genetically related to whom.

      In the case of cloning, however, there is but one ¡°parent.¡± The usually sad situation of the ¡°single-parent child¡± is here deliberately planned, and with a vengeance. In the case of self-cloning, the ¡°offspring¡± is, in addition, one¡¯s twin; and so the dreaded result of incest ¡ª to be parent to one¡¯s sibling ¡ª is here brought about deliberately, albeit without any act of coitus. Moreover, all other relationships will be confounded. What will father, grandfather, aunt, cousin, sister mean? Who will bear what ties and what burdens? What sort of social identity will someone have with one whole side ¡ª ¡±father¡¯s¡± or ¡°mother¡¯s¡± ¡ª necessarily excluded? It is no answer to say that our society, with its high incidence of divorce, remarriage, adoption, extramarital childbearing and the rest, already confounds lineage and confuses kinship and responsibility for children (and everyone else), unless one also wants to argue that this is, for children, a preferable state of affairs.

      Human cloning would also represent a giant step toward turning begetting into making, procreation into manufacture (literally, something ¡°handmade¡±), a process already begun with in vitro fertilization and genetic testing of embryos. With cloning, not only is the process in hand, but the total genetic blueprint of the cloned individual is selected and determined by the human artisans. To be sure, subsequent development will take place according to natural processes; and the resulting children will still be recognizably human. But we here would be taking a major step into making man himself simply another one of the man-made things. Human nature becomes merely the last part of nature to succumb to the technological project, which turns all of nature into raw material at human disposal, to be homogenized by our rationalized technique according to the subjective prejudices of the day.

      How does begetting differ from making? In natural procreation, human beings come together, complementarily male and female, to give existence to another being who is formed, exactly as we were, by what we are: living, hence perishable, hence aspiringly erotic, human beings. In clonal reproduction, by contrast, and in the more advanced forms of manufacture to which it leads, we give existence to a being not by what we are but by what we intend and design. As with any product of our making, no matter how excellent, the artificer stands above it, not as an equal but as a superior, transcending it by his will and creative prowess. Scientists who clone animals make it perfectly clear that they are engaged in instrumental making; the animals are, from the start, designed as means to serve rational human purposes. In human cloning, scientists and prospective ¡°parents¡± would be adopting the same technocratic mentality to human children: human children would be their artifacts.

      Such an arrangement is profoundly dehumanizing, no matter how good the product. Mass-scale cloning of the same individual makes the point vividly; but the violation of human equality, freedom and dignity are present even in a single planned clone. And procreation dehumanized into manufacture is further degraded by commodification, a virtually inescapable result of allowing babymaking to proceed under the banner of commerce. Genetic and reproductive biotechnology companies are already growth industries, but they will go into commercial orbit once the Human Genome Project nears completion. Supply will create enormous demand. Even before the capacity for human cloning arrives, established companies will have invested in the harvesting of eggs from ovaries obtained at autopsy or through ovarian surgery, practiced embryonic genetic alteration, and initiated the stockpiling of prospective donor tissues. Through the rental of surrogate-womb services, and through the buying and selling of tissues and embryos, priced according to the merit of the donor, the commodification of nascent human life will be unstoppable.

      Finally, and perhaps most important, the practice of human cloning by nuclear transfer ¡ª like other anticipated forms of genetic engineering of the next generation ¡ª would enshrine and aggravate a profound and mischievous misunderstanding of the meaning of having children and of the parent-child relationship. When a couple now chooses to procreate, the partners are saying yes to the emergence of new life in its novelty, saying yes not only to having a child but also, tacitly, to having whatever child this child turns out to be. In accepting our finitude and opening ourselves to our replacement, we are tacitly confessing the limits of our control. In this ubiquitous way of nature, embracing the future by procreating means precisely that we are relinquishing our grip, in the very activity of taking up our own share in what we hope will be the immortality of human life and the human species. This means that our children are not our children: they are not our property, not our possessions. Neither are they supposed to live our lives for us, or anyone else¡¯s life but their own. To be sure, we seek to guide them on their way, imparting to them not just life but nurturing, love, and a way of life; to be sure, they bear our hopes that they will live fine and flourishing lives, enabling us in small measure to transcend our own limitations. Still, their genetic distinctiveness and independence are the natural foreshadowing of the deep truth that they have their own and never-before-enacted life to live. They are sprung from a past, but they take an uncharted course into the future.

      Much harm is already done by parents who try to live vicariously through their children. Children are sometimes compelled to fulfill the broken dreams of unhappy parents; John Doe Jr. or the III is under the burden of having to live up to his forebear¡¯s name. Still, if most parents have hopes for their children, cloning parents will have expectations. In cloning, such overbearing parents take at the start a decisive step which contradicts the entire meaning of the open and forward-looking nature of parent-child relations. The child is given a genotype that has already lived, with full expectation that this blueprint of a past life ought to be controlling of the life that is to come. Cloning is inherently despotic, for it seeks to make one¡¯s children (or someone else¡¯s children) after one¡¯s own image (or an image of one¡¯s choosing) and their future according to one¡¯s will. In some cases, the despotism may be mild and benevolent. In other cases, it will be mischievous and downright tyrannical. But despotism ¡ª the control of another through one¡¯s will ¡ª it inevitably will be.

      Meeting some objections

      The defenders of cloning, of course, are not wittingly friends of despotism. Indeed, they regard themselves mainly as friends of freedom: the freedom of individuals to reproduce, the freedom of scientists and inventors to discover and devise and to foster ¡°progress¡± in genetic knowledge and technique. They want large-scale cloning only for animals, but they wish to preserve cloning as a human option for exercising our ¡°right to reproduce¡± ¡ª our right to have children, and children with ¡°desirable genes.¡± As law professor John Robertson points out, under our ¡°right to reproduce¡± we already practice early forms of unnatural, artificial and extramarital reproduction, and we already practice early forms of eugenic choice. For this reason, he argues, cloning is no big deal.

      We have here a perfect example of the logic of the slippery slope, and the slippery way in which it already works in this area. Only a few years ago, slippery slope arguments were used to oppose artificial insemination and in vitro fertilization using unrelated sperm donors. Principles used to justify these practices, it was said, will be used to justify more artificial and more eugenic practices, including cloning. Not so, the defenders retorted, since we can make the necessary distinctions. And now, without even a gesture at making the necessary distinctions, the continuity of practice is held by itself to be justificatory.

      The principle of reproductive freedom as currently enunciated by the proponents of cloning logically embraces the ethical acceptability of sliding down the entire rest of the slope ¡ª to producing children ectogenetically from sperm to term (should it become feasible) and to producing children whose entire genetic makeup will be the product of parental eugenic planning and choice. If reproductive freedom means the right to have a child of one¡¯s own choosing, by whatever means, it knows and accepts no limits.

      But, far from being legitimated by a ¡°right to reproduce,¡± the emergence of techniques of assisted reproduction and genetic engineering should compel us to reconsider the meaning and limits of such a putative right. In truth, a ¡°right to reproduce¡± has always been a peculiar and problematic notion. Rights generally belong to individuals, but this is a right which (before cloning) no one can exercise alone. Does the right then inhere only in couples? Only in married couples? Is it a (woman¡¯s) right to carry or deliver or a right (of one or more parents) to nurture and rear? Is it a right to have your own biological child? Is it a right only to attempt reproduction, or a right also to succeed? Is it a right to acquire the baby of one¡¯s choice?

      The assertion of a negative ¡°right to reproduce¡± certainly makes sense when it claims protection against state interference with procreative liberty, say, through a program of compulsory sterilization. But surely it cannot be the basis of a tort claim against nature, to be made good by technology, should free efforts at natural procreation fail. Some insist that the right to reproduce embraces also the right against state interference with the free use of all technological means to obtain a child. Yet such a position cannot be sustained: for reasons having to do with the means employed, any community may rightfully prohibit surrogate pregnancy, or polygamy, or the sale of babies to infertile couples, without violating anyone¡¯s basic human ¡°right to reproduce.¡± When the exercise of a previously innocuous freedom now involves or impinges on troublesome practices that the original freedom never was intended to reach, the general presumption of liberty needs to be reconsidered.

      We do indeed already practice negative eugenic selection, through genetic screening and prenatal diagnosis. Yet our practices are governed by a norm of health. We seek to prevent the birth of children who suffer from known (serious) genetic diseases. When and if gene therapy becomes possible, such diseases could then be treated, in utero or even before implantation ¡ª I have no ethical objection in principle to such a practice (though I have some practical worries), precisely because it serves the medical goal of healing existing individuals. But therapy, to be therapy, implies not only an existing ¡°patient.¡± It also implies a norm of health. In this respect, even germline gene ¡°therapy,¡± though practiced not on a human being but on egg and sperm, is less radical than cloning, which is in no way therapeutic. But once one blurs the distinction between health promotion and genetic enhancement, between so-called negative and positive eugenics, one opens the door to all future eugenic designs. ¡°To make sure that a child will be healthy and have good chances in life¡±: this is Robertson¡¯s principle, and owing to its latter clause it is an utterly elastic principle, with no boundaries. Being over eight feet tall will likely produce some very good chances in life, and so will having the looks of Marilyn Monroe, and so will a genius-level intelligence.

      Proponents want us to believe that there are legitimate uses of cloning that can be distinguished from illegitimate uses, but by their own principles no such limits can be found. (Nor could any such limits be enforced in practice.) Reproductive freedom, as they understand it, is governed solely by the subjective wishes of the parents-to-be (plus the avoidance of bodily harm to the child). The sentimentally appealing case of the childless married couple is, on these grounds, indistinguishable from the case of an individual (married or not) who would like to clone someone famous or talented, living or dead. Further, the principle here endorsed justifies not only cloning but, indeed, all future artificial attempts to create (manufacture) ¡°perfect¡± babies.

      A concrete example will show how, in practice no less than in principle, the so-called innocent case will merge with, or even turn into, the more troubling ones. In practice, the eager parents-to-be will necessarily be subject to the tyranny of expertise. Consider an infertile married couple, she lacking eggs or he lacking sperm, that wants a child of their (genetic) own, and propose to clone either husband or wife. The scientist-physician (who is also co-owner of the cloning company) points out the likely difficulties ¡ª a cloned child is not really their (genetic) child, but the child of only one of them; this imbalance may produce strains on the marriage; the child might suffer identity confusion; there is a risk of perpetuating the cause of sterility; and so on ¡ª and he also points out the advantages of choosing a donor nucleus. Far better than a child of their own would be a child of their own choosing. Touting his own expertise in selecting healthy and talented donors, the doctor presents the couple with his latest catalog containing the pictures, the health records and the accomplishments of his stable of cloning donors, samples of whose tissues are in his deep freeze. Why not, dearly beloved, a more perfect baby?

      The ¡°perfect baby,¡± of course, is the project not of the infertility doctors, but of the eugenic scientists and their supporters. For them, the paramount right is not the so-called right to reproduce but what biologist Bentley Glass called, a quarter of a century ago, ¡°the right of every child to be born with a sound physical and mental constitution, based on a sound genotype ... the inalienable right to a sound heritage.¡± But to secure this right, and to achieve the requisite quality control over new human life, human conception and gestation will need to be brought fully into the bright light of the laboratory, beneath which it can be fertilized, nourished, pruned, weeded, watched, inspected, prodded, pinched, cajoled, injected, tested, rated, graded, approved, stamped, wrapped, sealed and delivered. There is no other way to produce the perfect baby.

      Yet we are urged by proponents of cloning to forget about the science fiction scenarios of laboratory manufacture and multiple-copied clones, and to focus only on the homely cases of infertile couples exercising their reproductive rights. But why, if the single cases are so innocent, should multiplying their performance be so off-putting? (Similarly, why do others object to people making money off this practice, if the practice itself is perfectly acceptable?) When we follow the sound ethical principle of universalizing our choice ¡ª ¡±would it be right if everyone cloned a Wilt Chamberlain (with his consent, of course)? Would it be right if everyone decided to practice asexual reproduction?¡± ¡ª we discover what is wrong with these seemingly innocent cases. The so-called science fiction cases make vivid the meaning of what looks to us, mistakenly, to be benign.

      Though I recognize certain continuities between cloning and, say, in vitro fertilization, I believe that cloning differs in essential and important ways. Yet those who disagree should be reminded that the ¡°continuity¡± argument cuts both ways. Sometimes we establish bad precedents, and discover that they were bad only when we follow their inexorable logic to places we never meant to go. Can the defenders of cloning show us today how, on their principles, we will be able to see producing babies (¡°perfect babies¡±) entirely in the laboratory or exercising full control over their genotypes (including so-called enhancement) as ethically different, in any essential way, from present forms of assisted reproduction? Or are they willing to admit, despite their attachment to the principle of continuity, that the complete obliteration of ¡°mother¡± or ¡°father,¡± the complete depersonalization of procreation, the complete manufacture of human beings and the complete genetic control of one generation over the next would be ethically problematic and essentially different from current forms of assisted reproduction? If so, where and how will they draw the line, and why? I draw it at cloning, for all the reasons given.

      Ban the cloning of humans

      What, then, should we do? We should declare that human cloning is unethical in itself and dangerous in its likely consequences. In so doing, we shall have the backing of the overwhelming majority of our fellow Americans, and of the human race, and (I believe) of most practicing scientists. Next, we should do all that we can to prevent the cloning of human beings. We should do this by means of an international legal ban if possible, and by a unilateral national ban, at a minimum. Scientists may secretly undertake to violate such a law, but they will be deterred by not being able to stand up proudly to claim the credit for their technological bravado and success. Such a ban on clonal baby-making, moreover, will not harm the progress of basic genetic science and technology. On the contrary, it will reassure the public that scientists are happy to proceed without violating the deep ethical norms and intuitions of the human community.

      This still leaves the vexed question about laboratory research using early embryonic human clones, specially created only for such research purposes, with no intention to implant them into a uterus. There is no question that such research holds great promise for gaining fundamental knowledge about normal (and abnormal) differentiation, and for developing tissue lines for transplantation that might be used, say, in treating leukemia or in repairing brain or spinal cord injuries ¡ª to mention just a few of the conceivable benefits. Still, unrestricted clonal embryo research will surely make the production of living human clones much more likely. Once the genies put the cloned embryos into the bottles, who can strictly control where they go (especially in the absence of legal prohibitions against implanting them to produce a child)?

      I appreciate the potentially great gains in scientific knowledge and medical treatment available from embryo research, especially with cloned embryos. At the same time, I have serious reservations about creating human embryos for the sole purpose of experimentation. There is something deeply repugnant and fundamentally transgressive about such a utilitarian treatment of prospective human life. This total, shameless exploitation is worse, in my opinion, than the ¡°mere¡± destruction of nascent life. But I see no added objections, as a matter of principle, to creating and using cloned early embryos for research purposes, beyond the objections that I might raise to doing so with embryos produced sexually.

      And yet, as a matter of policy and prudence, any opponent of the manufacture of cloned humans must, I think, in the end oppose also the creating of cloned human embryos. Frozen embryonic clones (belonging to whom?) can be shuttled around without detection. Commercial ventures in human cloning will be developed without adequate oversight. In order to build a fence around the law, prudence dictates that one oppose ¡ª for this reason alone ¡ª all production of cloned human embryos, even for research purposes. We should allow all cloning research on animals to go forward, but the only safe trench that we can dig across the slippery slope, I suspect, is to insist on the inviolable distinction between animal and human cloning.

      Some readers, and certainly most scientists, will not accept such prudent restraints, since they desire the benefits of research. They will prefer, even in fear and trembling, to allow human embryo cloning research to go forward.

      Very well. Let us test them. If the scientists want to be taken seriously on ethical grounds, they must at the very least agree that embryonic research may proceed if and only if it is preceded by an absolute and effective ban on all attempts to implant into a uterus a cloned human embryo (cloned from an adult) to produce a living child. Absolutely no permission for the former without the latter.

      The National Bioethics Advisory Commission¡¯s recommendations regarding this matter should be watched with the greatest care. Yielding to the wishes of the scientists, the commission will almost surely recommend that cloning human embryos for research be permitted. To allay public concern, it will likely also call for a temporary moratorium ¡ª not a legislative ban ¡ª on implanting cloned embryos to make a child, at least until such time as cloning techniques will have been perfected and rendered ¡°safe¡± (precisely through the permitted research with cloned embryos). But the call for a moratorium rather than a legal ban would be a moral and a practical failure. Morally, this ethics commission would (at best) be waffling on the main ethical question, by refusing to declare the production of human clones unethical (or ethical). Practically, a moratorium on implantation cannot provide even the minimum protection needed to prevent the production of cloned humans.

      Opponents of cloning need therefore to be vigilant. Indeed, no one should be willing even to consider a recommendation to allow the embryo research to proceed unless it is accompanied by a call for prohibiting implantation and until steps are taken to make such a prohibition effective.

      Technically, the National Bioethics Advisory Commission can advise the president only on federal policy, especially federal funding policy. But given the seriousness of the matter at hand, and the grave public concern that goes beyond federal funding, the commission should take a broader view. (If it doesn¡¯t, Congress surely will.) Given that most assisted reproduction occurs in the private sector, it would be cowardly and insufficient for the commission to say, simply, ¡°no federal funding¡± for such practices. It would be disingenuous to argue that we should allow federal funding so that we would then be able to regulate the practice; the private sector will not be bound by such regulations. Far better, for virtually everyone concerned, would be to distinguish between research on embryos and baby-making, and to call for a complete national and international ban (effected by legislation and treaty) of the latter, while allowing the former to proceed (at least in private laboratories).

      The proposal for such a legislative ban is without American precedent, at least in technological matters, though the British and others have banned cloning of human beings, and we ourselves ban incest, polygamy and other forms of ¡°reproductive freedom.¡± Needless to say, working out the details of such a ban, especially a global one, would be tricky, what with the need to develop appropriate sanctions for violators. Perhaps such a ban will prove ineffective; perhaps it will eventually be shown to have been a mistake. But it would at least place the burden of practical proof where it belongs: on the proponents of this horror, requiring them to show very clearly what great social or medical good can be had only by the cloning of human beings.

      We Americans have lived by, and prospered under, a rosy optimism about scientific and technological progress. The technological imperative ¡ª if it can be done, it must be done ¡ª has probably served us well, though we should admit that there is no accurate method for weighing benefits and harms. Even when, as in the cases of environmental pollution, urban decay or the lingering deaths that are the unintended by-products of medical success, we recognize the unwelcome outcomes of technological advance, we remain confident in our ability to fix all the ¡°bad¡± consequences ¡ª usually by means of still newer and better technologies. How successful we can continue to be in such post hoc repairing is at least an open question. But there is very good reason for shifting the paradigm around, at least regarding those technological interventions into the human body and mind that will surely effect fundamental (and likely irreversible) changes in human nature, basic human relationships, and what it means to be a human being. Here we surely should not be willing to risk everything in the naive hope that, should things go wrong, we can later set them right.

      The president¡¯s call for a moratorium on human cloning has given us an important opportunity. In a truly unprecedented way, we can strike a blow for the human control of the technological project, for wisdom, prudence and human dignity. The prospect of human cloning, so repulsive to contemplate, is the occasion for deciding whether we shall be slaves of unregulated progress, and ultimately its artifacts, or whether we shall remain free human beings who guide our technique toward the enhancement of human dignity. If we are to seize the occasion, we must, as the late Paul Ramsey wrote, raise the ethical questions with a serious and not a frivolous conscience. A man of frivolous conscience announces that there are ethical quandaries ahead that we must urgently consider before the future catches up with us. By this he often means that we need to devise a new ethics that will provide the rationalization for doing in the future what men are bound to do because of new actions and interventions science will have made possible. In contrast a man of serious conscience means to say in raising urgent ethical questions that there may be some things that men should never do. The good things that men do can be made complete only by the things they refuse to do.

      ACKNOWLEDGEMENT

      Kass, Leon R. ¡°The Wisdom of Repugnance.¡± New Republic Vol. 216 Issue 22 (June 2, 1997).

      AUTHOR

      Leon R. Kass is the Addie Clark Harding Professor in The College and The Committee on Social Thought at The University of Chicago.


      The Reproductive Revolution
      Refs
      and further reading

      HOME
      Resources
      BLTC Research
      Liberal Eugenics
      Superhappiness?
      Utopian Surgery?
      The End of Suffering
      Wirehead Hedonism
      The Good Drug Guide
      The Abolitionist Project
      The Hedonistic Imperative
      The Reproductive Revolution
      MDMA: Utopian Pharmacology
      Transhumanism: Brave New World?
      Critique of Aldous Huxley's Brave New World

      e-mail
      dave@bltc.com

      ¡°You wait till Larry comes and I tell him my theory!¡± The bids, duly sealed, were given into the keeping of the commissary officer to be put in his safe, and kept until the day of judgment, when all being opened in public and in the presence of the aspirants, the lowest would[Pg 188] get the contract. It was a simple plan, and gave no more opportunity for underhand work than could be avoided. But there were opportunities for all that. It was barely possible¡ªthe thing had been done¡ªfor a commissary clerk or sergeant, desirous of adding to his pittance of pay, or of favoring a friend among the bidders, to tamper with the bids. By the same token there was no real reason why the commissary officer could not do it himself. Landor had never heard, or known, of such a case, but undoubtedly the way was there. It was a question of having the will and the possession of the safe keys. "Well, I believe our boys 's all right. They're green, and they're friskier than colts in a clover field, but they're all good stuff, and I believe we kin stand off any ordinary gang o' guerrillas. I'll chance it, anyhow. This's a mighty valuable train to risk, but it ought to go through, for we don't know how badly they may need it. You tell your engineer to go ahead carefully and give two long whistles if he sees anything dangerous." "Fine-looking lot of youngsters," he remarked. "They'll make good soldiers." "That's just what he was, the little runt, and we had the devil's own time finding him. What in Sam Hill did the Captain take him for, I'd like to know? Co. Q aint no nursery. Well, the bugler up at Brigade Headquarters blowed some sort of a call, and Skidmore wanted to know what it meant. They told him that it was an order for the youngest man in each company to come up there and get some milk for his coffee tomorrow morning, and butter for his bread. There was only enough issued for the youngest boys, and if he wanted his share he'd have to get a big hustle on him, for the feller whose nose he'd put out o' joint 'd try hard to get there ahead o' him, and get his share. So Skidmore went off at a dead run toward the sound of the bugle, with the boys looking after him and snickering. But he didn't come back at roll-call, nor at tattoo, and the smart Alecks begun to get scared, and abuse each other for setting up a job on a poor, innocent little boy. Osc Brewster and Ol Perry, who had been foremost in the trick had a fight as to which had been to blame. Taps come, and he didn't get back, and then we all became scared. I'd sent Jim Hunter over to Brigade Headquarters to look for him, but he came back, and said they hadn't seen anything of him there. Then I turned out the whole company to look for him. Of course, them too-awfully smart galoots of Co. A had to get very funny over our trouble. They asked why we didn't get the right kind of nurses for our company, that wouldn't let the members stray out of their sight? Why we didn't call the children in when the chickens went to roost, undress 'em, and tuck 'em in their little beds, and sing to 'em after they'd said 'Now I lay me down to sleep?' I stood it all until that big, hulking Pete Nasmith came down with a camp-kettle, which he was making ring like a bell, as he yelled out, 'Child lost! Child lost!' Behind him was Tub Rawlings singing, 'Empty's the cradle, baby's gone.' Then I pulled off my blouse and slung it into my tent, and told 'em there went my chevrons, and I was simply Scott Ralston, and able to lick any man in Co. A. One o' their Lieutenants came out and ordered them back to their quarters, and I deployed the company in a skirmish-line, and started 'em through the brush toward Brigade Headquarters. About three-quarters o' the way Osc Brewster and Ol Perry, when going through a thicket, heard a boy boo-hooing. They made their way to him, and there was little Skidmore sitting on a stump, completely confused and fagged out. He'd lost his way, and the more he tried to find it the worse he got turned around. They called out to him, and he blubbered out: 'Yes, it's me; little Pete Skidmore. Them doddurned fools in my company 've lost me, just as I've bin tellin' 'em right along they would, durn 'em.' Osc and Ol were so tickled at finding him that they gathered him up, and come whooping back to camp, carrying him every step of the way." And the rush stopped. Cadnan waited for a second, but there was no more. "Dara is not to die," he said. Then he saw Orion hanging over him, very low in the windy sky, shaking with frost. His eyes fixed themselves on the constellation, then gradually he became aware of the sides of a cart, of the smell of straw, of the movement of other bodies that sighed and stirred beside him. The physical experience was now complete, and soon the emotional had shaped itself. Memory came, rather sick. He remembered the fight, his terror, the flaming straw, the crowd that constricted and crushed him like a snake. His rage and hate rekindled, but this time without focus¡ªhe hated just everyone and everything. He hated the wheels which jolted him, his body because it was bruised, the other bodies round him, the stars that danced above him, those unknown footsteps that tramped beside him on the road. Farewell to Jane and Caroline!" HoME´óÏã½¶É«È˸ó ENTER NUMBET 0017
      wulila.com.cn
      www.dike3.net.cn
      www.daoba7.net.cn
      www.geian0.com.cn
      www.linke8.com.cn
      www.tiedu5.net.cn
      jlfhol.org.cn
      lezhi7.net.cn
      1ug.com.cn
      520ka.com.cn
      sex007dh 黄色以及金发大波 狠狠插衅小说 zui淫当的女人 在线电影西野翎 狠狠射套图 偷拍老外打野炮 能bt下载的黄色网址有什么 色无码电影 WWW.SHLSHW.COM WWW.AVTAOBAO.CA WWW.9ZY.COM WWW.BBB012.COM WWW.IKUYY.COM WWW.QIMI567.COM WWW.001561.COM WWW.CYMPZJ.COM WWW.XIAOMINGLU.COM WWW.QZXSHG.COM WWW.234ZA.COM WWW.DAKCN.COM WWW.LQCYSK.COM WWW.PNZWK.COM WWW.MMM70.COM WWW.223326.COM WWW.BBYLU.COM WWW.JSZXA.COM WWW.995NN.COM WWW.LWLM.COM WWW.9LALA.COM 偷拍打炮 亚洲电亚洲电影一级三级片 电车千人斩美女 9797sb 亚洲天堂姐姐图片 美女馒头缝 成人社www6666caocom 人体色色小色网 爱丽丝丝袜 大黑吊双非亚裔美女 91超碰自拍91agaobiz 在车上强奸黄色小说 555dvd版 4hu8ftp 乱伦孙婆在线97 天天日久久射精品 色网AV免费在线 三国影视韩国 xiao七七小说网 234XXXX mm付费影院 好硬啊受不了舒服快点嗯插揉捏舔换妻3p 非洲三级片大全 老师媳妇的性奴 三级片女秘书 丝袜黄色图片区 姬岛琉璃香在线观看 女儿当妻子乱伦 窝窝娱乐网 邪恶少女漫画全色彩群奸 尻bi 狠狠色无极 大姨子偷欢 231avav 草莓100视频在线播放caonila 风骚少妇掰开私处让你操 婷婷五月花亚洲色图 大爷av影院免费观看 色忧忧av国产 色姐姐色妹妹激情电影在线播放 12345cccom 播乐子超在线 免费伦理小说母子片 www7878kf 96色色 977AV在线视频 求免费成人电影app像猫咪av一样的 色月丁香网 5678台湾老伦理在线 wwwhw好日子啪啪 成人影院草榴 萝莉乱伦小说网站 3d欧美动漫 姑xx卡通 奇米影音第四色7e7ucom 都市激情乱伦小说在线看 亚洲武侠古典在线播放 julia超碰在线观看 wwwggg03 看到b的美女操b 亚洲儿童哭泣 国产第一页1024网址 婷婷夜夜撸 wwwbbb75com 干丰满少妇真爽 内射美女骚穴在线视频 最新免费成人性爱网址 猛男熟妇乱伦电影片 3p无码啪啪啪 日本少女激情电影兽欲 淫水流的老婆很骚下载 进进出出嫩穴p 三级无码高清 WWWRRR777COM 冲田杏梨的巨乳舔频屏吧 磁力链接成都兰桂坊 亚洲色图校长 外国妇女的阴部图展示 夜夜干夜夜go2048com 991色色直 亚洲成人综合综合套图校园春色 成人电影偷拍自拍亚洲图片欧美图 乱操逼 免费79dodo 熟女乱伦偷拍逼 taiwansexvideo 伎逼射精图怕 长谷川由奈写真 成人免费电影幼交同志 两性做爱图片哪里有 美国大胆电影 影音先锋人肏肏狗 宫如敏全套高清照片 庐江艳照门迅雷种子 与空共同生活24小时 狗鸡巴肏女人 激情诱惑美女影音先锋 人体艺木l 与淑女乱伦 日本大逼逼裸体艺术 32式夫妻性姿势动态图 婷婷五月成人社区 外国美女口交20p pisay pao演过什么 9da51f8e00001217 露出小屄了 强奸美女小屄 美女图片都不穿xiaoshuo 女教师厕所偷拍图片 乡村操穴小说 拍网友骚女人 父女叉屄 国外全裸演唱会视频 论理性与情感照片视频 人妻 亚洲 qvod 有没有阿娇的阴部图片 东北成人网论坛 五月天影院快播 磁力链接 在线播放 学生和老师天天做爱 斗战神猴子棍系加点 顾雅莉 阳光大姐月嫂培训 国家海洋局北海分局 插幼幼淫网 少妇美穴15p 操大黑逼逼 clsq123 欧美男图片吧 屄最黑女明星 幼种子zip 汤芳大胆艺术照 日本美女下体艺术摄影图 日本美女秀百屄图 美女丝袜密室狠狠撸色图 肉棒操骚逼 包射日本美女 小明看看最新手机页面 葵实野理无码流出 陪我撸影院播放 哥哥操图片 成人嘻嘻导航 WWWHHH097COM 乱了儿子 xingbiantaiwangzhan 谁空间内有爽图 操紧身妹 换妻母子 大胆女同性恋影级 伦理琪琪琪影 www38popoom 撸撸撸两炮 久爱微拍 新掌酷手机手机电影 超碰百年好合网址 老少男女乱伦 快活宫 淫荡美女情妇 偷偷鲁网友 三级片嫩模做爱视频成人片 偷偷撸狠狠撸在线色图 狠狠射性感美女屁股图片 撸操女人 奇米影视775me9999abc 日了妈妈和姐姐动漫 成人黄色电影国产片 征服刘亦菲母女 强奸乱伦AV网址 越南美女大胆裸体人体艺术 激情影院20秒试看 哥哥色cm 狼窝yingyuan 幼女与成人性生活小说 激情五月姐姐seffhhggcom 同学阿姨的美脚 偷怕自拍国产精品magnet 色g有声小说 三岔口有声小说 樱井莉亚学制精灵 h网 小说 开心五月天图 东京热0327 东京热怎么 5300看黄片 蝴蝶谷网 色色快播 色域H网 90聚导航 性生活知识 一个色电影 日本美腿丝袜 哇嘎成人社区 台湾佬中文娱乐网 欲望之城成人社区 777米奇 百撸 松本麻里奈中文字幕种子链接 超级轮乱家庭漫画 YOYO视频磁力链接 234top 色欲宗和合网 人人干人人操人人麽 女同天天啪 色爱52v 日本学生av 小乔影院福利地址 秋霞床上 性交视频极品 情欲媽 日本岳母大奶免费视频 日韩 偷拍 自拍 在线 在线 无码 国产自拍 丝袜 中文字幕 日本一本道在线免费看 日本曰B 日本女优和黑人操逼16p AV800000 2019AV云盘 0855kk 远坂凛 做爱 100名日本女优视频 人间中毒末册剪版在线 白户英里奈链接 男人你懂得在线看 午夜免费57 www179nncon 色鬼国内自拍在线观看 国产自拍在线成观看 免费黄色视频好屌色 222av tb 国产自拍磁力合计 电脑在线观看国产自拍 青青草鸡巴要要在线观看 china夫妻性 回校的地铁上撩起了女同座裙子漫画 久久爱水莱丽在线播放 熟女做爱图片小视屏 调教日记6 番号 坏木坏木木集百万潮流小说 639影院福利片 大尺度同志在线观看 youbbb/cm 影音先锋 91 娃玖电影手机在线 4438x免费成人网暴力 猪小明墙 大桥未久Av 在线 91老司机sm 柚木提娜剧情在线播放 决胜 magnet 处女失身记视频 福利影院闪现福利 大鸡巴小鲜肉约炮极品丝袜高跟美女玩角色扮 地下痴女3d链接 成人影院在观线看 大香蕉网站被老公的上司连续侵犯七天已经丧失理性 国产成人啪啪自拍 yuojii视频 4438Xx12C〇m 色女人偷拍 k8经典邱淑贞 mm小视频在线观看 色哥vvv68 4438x手机在线观看 www奔驰宝马成人网站 日本搭讪在线视频 泽艺影院在线观看 主播网红在线影院 3D动漫成人视频 91大神C仔之极品黑丝高跟年轻豪门女家教 教育网人体艺术 香港奥门a片 国产自拍在线播放无需播放器 乱伦人妻在线视频 52秒拍福利视频优衣库 日韩无码欧美在线丝袜百度云 岛国爱情动作片卵蛋 7777,gao,com 拍拍影院三级片 韩国青草 4480国产自拍三级 现在能看黄色视频的播放器 小V欲女规视频 想要零用钱妹妹帮素股。结果爽到自行插入肉到爽番号 性交视频网战 校院武侠作爱视频 久草特黄免费视频 温碧霞b cup 国产偷拍亚洲华人自拍 美丽人妻少妇被插视频 成人黄色一级电视剧 A片红 楼 肏b视频 操好丝袜 国内自拍性交视频 仓持结爱高潮跌幅湿漉漉的性爱 视频密码 哥爱搞搞网在线看 美国伦理精彩剪辑在线 有没有a片网站 羔羊医生 magnet 我的性感女秘书窝窝伦理电影 厕所直插下面视频 被窝理论电影300集 sm 亚洲 欧美 少妇 女神平面模特李x熙视频 插美少妇小穴 杨幂在线永久视频在线 网红花臂纹身美女大花猫SM微拍视频 ddd528kkk 日本版红楼梦成人在线 情趣磁力 magnet 日本老女人丝祙 俺去啦在线不要播放器 做爱视频鸡吧插的好舒服啊 同性在线播放 宅男成人福利网址导航 袭击女教师水菜丽在线看 全世界最火的小黄片视频网站 feexx 有欧美爆乳的电影 主播 磁力链接 mp4 亚洲最大福利视频道网 苍进空磁力链接下载 国产系医生护士搞在线 女生资源 91日逼视 免费天海翼视频在线观看 暗拍美女潜规则视频 国产网红主播激情自拍 悠悠色播 免费成人斤 成人手机视频5× 日本强奸妇女有哪些在线视频 国产中老年男同视频在线观看 Xxx经典国语网 美女被黑人操音乐 色欧美免费小视频 六月丁香深深爱在线 青青草大香蕉公开视频 家庭乱情王玉霞 aaa47大片 黄瓜视频官网 好看成人短视频 片a本日女小妹 9200dy 韩国男女搞基直播 日本老熟妇性欲 setongxue 帅哥抽插 悠悠av资源 骑手黄色网站 乐播av 成人网战链接 水仙网罗马影音先锋 人与兽bt种子 下载 秘杜mmsscom 国产自拍免费播放网站 好屌操在线影院 国产在线俱乐部 a片降头电影 x25rrrr 女人摸自己的阴天天影音 惹惹成人视屏 北条麻妃无码神马在线观看 无码性爱视频播放器 在线屋里番在线观看 wohejiaoshimamadeseqinggushi 77mp4 sixt 小身材影音先锋 秋霞无码理论欧美电影 4480福利动作影院 日本成人性爱视频在线 caoporn视频在线 国产自拍 三级黄久久免费视频 大黑逼色导航 和幼女做爱英语怎么说 美少女操屄图片 huangseyijipianwuzetian 哪里能看到乱伦小说 kaixinjiqingwangzhan 淫色基地成人电影 李宗瑞刘亦菲 学姐教会我内射 干熟女大屁股 天天射综合网 天天射 护士做爱艳照 qq阴茎表情 9797滛滛网 张雨筱露逼图片 极品少妇乱淫 色丑月 激情妹妹狠操社区 雯雅婷 p 胆大人体阴道 美女医生的性生活故事 熟女俱乐部母子家庭乱伦 欧美老女人爱大炮 小泽玛利亚经典是哪一部 外国女人的阴道比中国女人的大 波多野结衣酒店性爱图片 花花操逼 性爱网亚洲 波多野结衣蝴蝶逼 哪个主播露点 看日bb电影 路边偷拍美女脱丝袜 亚洲美女bb人体艺术大bb图片精选 少妇肉体视频图片小说 全球最美阴毛彩绘百度 脱摸吻揉舔插射爽 最新先锋强奸乱伦 sao1314next 美女的逼骚吗 a片 迅雷下载 ok3699jiunengshuangle 重庆赵红霞真实照片 钮扣包装机 cs15中文版官方下载 为自己疗伤 裸体照下面带毛 夫妻口交视频 换妻群交老婆被干了 西西美女写真人体艺术 内射粉木耳图 性感h漫女 做爱图片大全 黑人抽插女大学生 台湾天目为何油亮是否对人体有害 长谷川惠美全裸图片 偷拍走光露逼 性感的公鸡在日本爱 日本女优吉吉 欧美huangsetupian 肥胖大妈试玩一下16p 张筱宇裸体图 14岁少女午夜操逼逼图 1919go全集wctoupai 美女明星内地艳门照被奸 莲苍h 日本香奈图片 恒荣半岛影院 吃六神丸壮阳吗 有一部日本a片变态 大自由门 玩女人逼爽吗 陆婷婷的新故事 类似91pore 橘梨纱pron 少妇成熟高跟 美女露b人体艺术图片 和骚人妻偷情 另类偷拍自拍女厕所 亚洲情图片插插 妹妹水好多三级片 tube8jianpanhome 欧美孕妇裸体写真 女人美穴图片 苍井空av电影里快播 亚洲操逼辣图 欧美人体露美穴图片 WWWZ9191COM 十五岁女孩嫩穴 影音先锋草p片 色成人激情小说 中华明星合成联盟 强奸幼女小说淫魔 欧激情美 插入成人图 色qing3jipian 苍井そら 全97本番 エスワン12时间コンプリ━萣est av撸色2013 谁有一本道的网站 rtys人体艺术 kaori无码 发红屄 快乐网 亿性家社区视频 放心医院两性真人视频 女神约泡系列 成人影ya 叶子楣人体写真下载 母子猛干 女主播水仙先锋影音 wwese华人视频com 看电影lai5566 伦理微电影magnet 快播变态女子监狱 绿色无毒的av电影网址 亚洲偷少妇偷拍网 淫荡艳妻 xzzlynmp4 pv990下载地址 婷色艺术 日本涩情pia 欧美激情丝袜电影 操台湾妹子综合网站 欧美超爽图 欧美熟女高跟骚屄 大波少妇背着老公与我偷情自拍 kukucao网址 ab偷拍自拍 色五月激情五月开心五月开心色播深爱五月色播五月 插逼进行操 SM之拳交妹妹后庭花 黑人大吊手机影视 干里赖你个集掰你个蓝交 av插肛视频播放 酷娱乐影视 日本大胆av人体写真 当着外人的面插入下载 淫荡的性奴熟妇 人妻野外调教小说 美味的邂逅秒播影视 淫色娟娟 36d大乃网欧美AV视频 美女奶子videombaiducom 我妹让我插进去了图 www2C33eeecom cqopor 人狗大战伦理片下载 偸拍女性上厕所大便 姐姐性教育之熟女 宝来美雪ed2k 亚洲电亚洲电影一级三级片 华为网盘饭岛爱 色一涩888手机版 AV教师有中文字幕 人肉医奴隶 夜猫免费视频在线观看 哥想撸久草 极品少妇赤裸自慰 videos日本小女孩 能免费看av的软件 俩性生活迅雷下载图片 白色帝国论坛 久草手机在线观视频dz003com 英语老师小骚货 岳母比老婆好中文字幕 激情五月色视频www031ncom 家庭乱伦丝袜文章 金瓶梅成人性爱电影 s3zzbbcom xedd5com 性奴玛丽奥特曼 深圳合租房换女妻 久久爱情电影 超碰邻居熟女自拍偷拍在线 母子乱伦自拍网站 h七七p七cn 中出人妻20P 偷干人妻网 www69avcom 成人三级图 光棍电影手机观看小姨子 插入技巧小说 360色图 日本网站网站大全A片wwwc5508com 日本打炮射精热视频 黑人影院无需播放器 2233p x77135com 少女日本电影影音先锋 日韩av手机在线 头交是真的还是假的 麻生希婚纱影音先锋 欧美成人图像 888840c○m 在线卡通第一页 天天啪啪 日本AV色星熟女英文名排行榜 最大淫网 [18P]下一篇 线上干短片 搜索wwwjjxxoocom DBEB045 色色妹7 人人dvd 美国色图操操操 av天堂1024 苍月战士一路向西 人体mrtzcc 换妻日逼片 国产偷拍亚洲Av 苹果范冰冰电影完整 妹妹五月四房色伯图片 淫荡激情夫妻书库 3p性交 W66cccom 绑作者不详 啪啪啪在线兔费 草莓影音免费视频在线观看 关于处女破处的三级片 vvvv900 h动漫电梯小姐在线观看 www·bbb866·com下载 干女人逼视频在线 色少妇巨乳www23xxoocom 大鸡吧老公操动态图片 Www撸妹妹撸 男人体艺术偷拍 幼童H网 想屄图 美咲结衣重口味 大片上床 地下歌舞团黑酒吧演出 被迫坐肉棒 下鸡巴操屄p 裸体少女的屄 日本电影父女乱 白石瞳百度音影 熟女 性爱影院 888kkkk mimisechengrendaohang 呦呦同志种子 caoxisaobi 美女爱上大屌球 舒淇人体阴部 � 老婆和女儿的小穴 操小姐小嫩逼 老农和几个大学色女生的淫荡生活 波多野结衣洗澡做爱 狠狠色欧美色图 丝袜淫乱都市 东京热吉吉影音2233b 123美女se图 美少女色片 第四色 高清裸体炮图 ww777cccc777 鱼鱼发乱伦有声小说 华人家庭乱伦小说 � 跪求张柏芝艳照门视频 色 五月天 婷婷人与动物 美妇图册熟女相册 2015最新黄色笑话 成人在线国外 黑b 舔岳母亲 肥穴h图 xxoous你懂的小说 WWW_MAYAW_COM a片合集迅雷合集 操五十八岁大妈快播 多原爱 富士康厂妹qq群 cs16地图编辑器 poynjizzjizzpoyn 插女子网 吉吉av色片 新闻两片嫩肉 红音萤影音先锋 同性恋操屁股的图片 黄色网址无簿日韩 性爱狠撸撸小说 鸡巴肏屄的图片 seqingshi频 我和小姐乱伦 狠狠干自拍 明星合成王艳 芭芭拉人体艺术第一季 撸撸撸射 学校骚妇被插爽了 撸哥妹短片在线 强奸同学母小说 教师操屄 av小池郎 藤田凉子黑人 法哥操美女 张柏芝qovd完整版 上海自然博物馆4d影院 把屄拍照给别人看的感觉 泽国中学叶坚强老师的照片谁有 玩弄姚笛的屁眼 性交真人视频过程 插黑木耳高清图片18p 什么浏览器能下载嘼交片啊 svssex 淫姐姐色色电影网站 弟弟用力插妹妹 冰冷热带鱼146分钟种子 18xx24cccc 操苍井空嫩屄 七七色原图 小姨子的神秘三角地带 吉吉成人影沓 黑丝足txt 风流老徐娘15P 操十岁幼nv小说 四房播播伦理片 偷拍网国产视频m520xxbinfo 韩国女主播干妹妹 空姐干爹 长篇连载淫荡人妻驱灵师 有强奸内容的小黄文 大肛门欧美 尤丁香在线 青楼社区强奸 btyy sx黄色 反恐精英伊莎邪恶图片 白洁骆冰 青春少女下阴全裸图片 小明看看奥门 干漂亮老婆作者不详 都市激情亚洲色图花和尚 gggg555成人网 插妈妈在线视 欧美暴力性爱AV 日韩成人另类在线视频 日撸百度 恋母爱诗 真抢实弹福生日 韩国露点女主播有哪些 我的女朋友叫我搞她妈妈 熟年夫妇性爱日记 性春馆剑道 中文字幕影ckplayer在线观看 韩日女优大奶视频 手机快播能看的h网 快播h网大全 开心五月天激网 l酒色网 最近老看黄片 撸撸黄色小说 色五月激情五月天 浪妹社区 90后电影 我淫我乐综合 绝色影吧(荐) 爱搞机 凹凸AV电影手机在线下载 爱的色放西瓜 凉宫琴音在线看 动态图玉免社会app下载 人人草人人做 女大学生破处黄色视频 全裸美女照正面视频发 秋霞电影网伦理片手机版 青青情侣自拍视频在线 曰本黄大片p在线 淫撸女 影音先锋 熟女系列 日本乳汁作爱视频 日本亚洲欧洲另类 hd porn 91亚洲 轮奸骚逼太爽了大骚逼 韩国女主播 平台大全 姐汁 情艺中心在线紧急 这个杀手不太冷动态壁纸 4438×全国最大电 大尺度捏胸揉胸漫画 灰色毛衣在线完整版 国产欧美自拍 国模私拍露点视频 666668888888福利视频 近亲相奸大作战番号 日本AV黄图 mp4 让我添大胸添屁股的视频 亚洲不卡视频大全 女人乳头穿环视频播放 免费xing直播 黄色视频激情小说 热产热国产自拍 极品辣妈淫语约炮 旧谷露影院av欧美 亚洲视频人妻 丁香夜色 自拍骚逼 mp4 黑人影片三级黄色 717伦理片午夜福利剧场 猫味网站 无码背得心色香 毛片高清免费完整版1080p 87国产一区 91 E杯气美女 一色屋色色资源站 好色电影院菲菲 精子窝 网红主播自慰视频 武侠古典 万色屋 大香蕉福利电影 福利莫青视频在线 大香蕉丝袜亚洲国产 大香蕉95视频在线 yazhousutu 饭冈加奈子强制生中出 日本一级色片 李丽珍在线电影 magnet 久久爱视频10 粗大的做爱体验 我和阿姨乱伦视频 丁香五月在线观看线 成人丁香五月 百度 抽插在线视频 婷婷视频在线观看 福利资源大厅 艺校小女生在线视频 黑色男女福利 啪啪久啪啪精品99 淫湿影院 啪啪啪视频免费在线观看无码 日本少妇在家被强奷 偷拍自插 理论韩影库 wwwabc300cd 欧美AV日韩AV国产AV在,线 午夜情深深医院 1138x成年网 操丰满浪叫在线 京香中文字幕无删减 中国javhd 蝌蚪网无限看视频 AISS模特索菲 在线福利视频 女a片 拍拍拍噜噜噜 轻经操穴视频视 高清无码在线免安装 一路夜蒲 bt 相对宇宙 露点 求番号大胸妹子被裸体关在门外然后被强奸 秋霞电影网达达网 2综合色 色无极偷窥 av圣爱天堂2014 怡红院成人av电影 团鬼六拷问贵夫人 我肏小姨子的嫩屄 百变女神魅心户外大马路 萝莉自慰视频大全 小明发看看加密网址一 天狼影院三级片 1313电影网韩国演义圈 小孕妇seamp孕交 先锋影音冲田杏梨骑乘 淫秽视屏 五福影院其它地址 高清自拍尿尿 magnet 找av123导航 午夜按摩中字 大白逼做爱视频 和ye123一样的网站 uu福利 !密码 www,477,mm,con rosi视频002 快乐色 偷窥自拍777 色香蕉无码色 国产自拍在线诱惑 国语高清居家享受嗲嗲的女友口爆服务 国产偷拍白拍 自拍自摸国产 h0930 番号 丁香茶五月天 caoporn未满 色色色干人人 被窝屋 苹果手机成人免费视频 美女路b沟视频 找性交小姐性交巴西 俄罗斯最骚最黄的黄色录像视频 天天吊妞o 3344rq最新地址 啪啪啪视频网站上去衣图片给我看看你的照片看看你现在在哪里番acg 乳头文胸性诱惑 女神操逼视频在线 韩国女主播和闺蜜爱抚 网红啪啪啪视频大全 巴西做爱视频 家教老师秘书空姐护士美女满足表情性高潮视频 ROSI在线播放VIP 操逼福利区 国内第一人重口变态女王周晓琳 本庄优花黑人在线 老外啪啪内射视频 恋夜秀场美女同性恋做爱视频 四虎影院手机小视频福利 静宸制服私拍 赵铬扯肚兒视频 美国炮长 本站立足于 ooxxwangzhan mb27ba0 情人天堂 立足于美利坚合众国鲁 青青社区国产自拍 淫操初音女神 纯h视频免费 色佬久爱视频av天天看 色博士 色妞妞线官网 伦理片2344 色麒麟无码帝国av影院 毛片a片鸡巴插洞 美国偷拍三级网站酒店叫服务打飞机 精品操B 伦理福利在线365 李美淑左爱 都市激情校园人妻亚洲 黑丝袜伦理 韩国人做爱免费视频 欧美黑人性生活一级黄片 最近上传最新视频在线观看 蛇精潮巢漫画 freepronvv 激情小说激情图片激情电影 老色鬼导航最全面 冲田杏梨巨乳女教师91 偶偶福利电影 黄色小视频美利坚合众国 飘花影院ipad 黑哥tv登录740 好深好烫好棒顶到不行 好看做爱视频 今永纱奈AV电影迅雷 下载 夫妻露脸偷窥自拍 xingjiaomuzi 毛片123 dd55aa FC2云播手机在线 sex video ht 18禁无码里番在线观看 国内自拍 淫荡骚逼 有关性爱视频 郑州酒店有小姐决赛开始视频让妻子看什么连续剧播放视频 美女教师种子下载 mp4 日本三人交视频yes 秘杜mmsscom 秒播福利手机在线播放 好屌丝好屌操 韩国女主播CK买肉舞 国产偷拍少妇磁力迅雷下载 古装三级伦理在线电影 欧美影院高清 在线免费小视屏 色色风在线播放 日本a级无码 zaixianshipin wuma 大吊色 黄图香蕉影院 成人福利分享 髛屄视频 早乙女由依(萝莉) 777奇米影天堂 超成人触碰 穿连体袜的素人完整版 欧美一本道无码高清视频 日本sm在线调教视频 omeidonwu qj无码 世界最大胆美女人体艺术 人体艺术激情欧美 时间停止器系列先锋 黑木麻衣社长 日撸神 亚洲色图台湾佬 大胆人体艺术韩国美女明星图片 义弟内射嫂子 www骚嫂子com 国亩欢大胆露阴毛 成人大尺度gif 妇乱艺术穴图 公然妄想曝苍井空先锋影音 卖屄俱乐部 关之琳演过哪些三影级 韩青青医生 黑人夫妇宾馆作爱视频 哪里有韩国女主播种子 偷拍男按摩师视频